Suchergebnisse
Filter
20 Ergebnisse
Sortierung:
In Defence of Open Theism
In: Science, Religion & Culture: SRC, Band 4, Heft 2
ISSN: 2055-222X
Response to Reviewers
In: European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Band 6, Heft 2, S. 51-63
Précis of Mind, Brain, and Free Will
In: European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Band 6, Heft 2, S. 1-3
Gregory Palamas and our Knowledge of God
In: Studia humana: quarterly journal ; SH, Band 3, Heft 1, S. 3-12
ISSN: 2299-0518
Abstract
Although Gregory wrote very little about this. he acknowledged that natural reason can lead us from the orderliness of the physical world to the existence of God; in this, he followed the tradition of Athanasius and other Greek fathers. Unlike Aquinas, he did not seek to present the argument a; deductive: in fact his argument is inductive, and of die same kind as - we now realize - scientists and historians use when they argue from phenomena to then explanatory cause. Gregory wrote hardly anything about how one could obtain knowledge of the truths of the Christian revelation by arguments from non-question-beggining premises; but in his conversations with the Turks he showed that he believed that there are good arguments of this kind. Almost all of Gregory's writing about knowledge of God concerned how one could obtain this by direct access in prayer: this access, he held is open especially to monks, but to a considerable degree also to all Christians who follow the divine commandments.
What Kind of Necessary Being Could God Be?
In: European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Band 4, Heft 2, S. 1-18
A logically impossible sentence is one which entails a contradiction, a logically necessary sentence is one whose negation entails a contradiction, and a logically possible sentence is one which does not entail a contradiction. Metaphysically impossible, necessary and possible sentences are ones which become logically impossible, necessary, or possible by substituting what I call informative rigid designators for uninformative ones. It does seem very strongly that a negative existential sentence cannot entail a contradiction, and so 'there is a God' cannot be a metaphysically necessary truth. If it were such a truth, innumerable other sentences which seem paradigm examples of logically possible sentences, such as 'no one knows everything' would turn out to be logically impossible. The only way in which God could be a logically necessary being is if there were eternal necessary propositions independent of human language or God's will, such that the proposition that there is no God would entail – via propositions inaccessible to us – a contradiction. But if there were such propositions, God would have less control over the universe than he would have otherwise.
God as the Simplest Explanation of the Universe
In: European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Band 2, Heft 1, S. 1-24
Inanimate explanation is to be analysed in terms of substances having powers and liabilities to exercise their powers under certain conditions; while personal explanation is to be analysed in terms of persons, their beliefs, powers, and purposes. A crucial criterion for an explanation being probably true is that it is (among explanations leading us to expect the data) the simplest one. Simplicity is a matter of few substances, few kinds of substances, few properties (including powers and liabilities), few kinds of properties, and mathematically simple relations between properties. Explanation of the existence of the universe by the agency of God provides the simplest kind of personal explanation there can be, and one simpler than any inanimate explanation. I defend this view more thoroughly than previously in light of recent challenges.
Editorial
In: European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Band 1, Heft 1, S. i-ii
The Value of Synchronic Justification
In: Epistemic Justification, S. 152-164
The Value of Diachronic Justification
In: Epistemic Justification, S. 165-191
Theories of Synchronic Justification
In: Epistemic Justification, S. 9-31